Saturday, November 16, 2013

Foucault/Derrida exchange

The group begins with the context of Derrida’s paper and the break between the two philosophers. The discussion proceeds with (I) the analysis of Descartes’ passages quoted in Foucault, (II) Foucault’s reading of these passages, and (III) Derrida’s critique of Foucault.

I. Madness in Descartes:

The group has difficulty in dealing with Descartes, having not read him recently. The members identify, however, that the discussion of madness (in relation to doubt) precede cogito.

II. Foucault’s reading of Descartes

Foucault’s argument: the exclusion of madness from the discourse of reason – an act of silencing. This happens with the distinct way in which Descartes overcomes errors such as dreams. What differentiates madness from, say, dreams?
           
1. Body: in dreams I have a sense of body and a control of my body, albeit deranged or distended, whereas in madness the body doesn’t belong to me.
2. Recoverability: Dreams are subject to errors that can be corrected (confusion, illusion, etc.). When I wake up my deranged and distended body is corrected, whereas madness remains uncorrected. Errors outside reason can’t be corrected; therefore, madness is external to reason.

Then, one cannot suppose one is mad, for the condition of possibility of having the thought of madness is reason.

The group thinks that Foucault might be reading back cogito these passages, while Descartes is still developing the concept of doubt.

III. Derrida’s critique of Foucault

Derrida’s argument: one can’t do a historical/social analysis of madness as a concept or idea.
Madness as an absent present drives philosophical discourse. It is a motivating principle of the philosophical project as the essential other of discourse. It is in opposition to speech (65). It is before language and discourse; it is that which we do violence.

Thus, when we talk about it we’re putting the straightjacket to madness, incorporating it into discourse. This is what Foucault does, as he is speaking within discourse and thus reason. Therefore, by bracketing madness Descartes is more sincere than Foucault who takes it up, assuming that you can talk about it. Descartes in fact performs the reality of madness in the philosophical discourse.


The group acknowledges the deconstructionist tendencies that Derrida would later develop, agreeing with certain aspects of his critique. And yet, how Derrida’s intervention contributes to (or even relates to) the general discussion of the containment of the mad man or Foucault’s larger project is undetermined.

Thursday, November 7, 2013

Foucault, "Discourse on Language" (1971)

We began the session with several questions, many of them relating to the concept of truth:
1.     Would it be useful to map out the text, basically?
2.     Foucault suggests that “it is always possible one could speak the truth in a void” (224).  Is this possible and/or consistent with his philosophical project?
3.     Does Foucault understand himself to be a “monster on the prowl,” in the sense that he is speaking the truth, but not within the discursive framework of his time (223-224)?
4.     How does Foucault himself fit within his own definition of “the author”?  Is he an author, or fictional, as he suggests “authors” in fact are?
5.     What is the relationship between the author-function and spoken language?  Is there a difference between the truth that can be found in written narratives, and truth that is spoken?
6.     What does it mean to say that “the theme of the founding subject permits us to elide the reality of discourse” (227)?
7.     Foucault talks about logophobia and logophilia (228-229), which is strange since he rarely speaks of affect.  How is this significant?

We then outlined a sketchy framework of Foucault’s method in the lecture:
1.     Three sets of procedures to regulate/control discourse:
a.     External Exclusions
                                               i.     Prohibitions:
1.     Objects
2.     Rituals
3.     Expertise
                                             ii.     Divisions/rejections
1.     Oppositions btw. reason/madness, e.g.
                                            iii.     Will to Truth
b.     Internal Rules
                                               i.     Commentary
                                             ii.     Author
                                            iii.     Disciplines
c.     Rarefaction among speaking subjects
                                               i.     Ritual
                                             ii.     Fellowships of discourse
                                            iii.     Doctrine
                                            iv.     Social appropriation of discourse
2.     Several reinforcements of these regulations within modern philosophy
a.     Indicts Cartesians, phenomenologists, and Hegelianism
3.     Methodological principles to counter discursive regulations:
a.     Eventually yields two analytic methods: critical and genealogical (critical here seems to mean archaeological)
4.     Ends with hagiography of Hyppolite.

We then opened up into a broader discussion of Foucault’s aims, especially concerning the phrase Will to Truth:
1.     What does Will to Truth mean?  Why is it a will to truth, not the production of truth?
a.     We then debated whether Foucault is lamenting the production of truth in our modern discourse, and nostalgic for its production in, for instance, ancient Greece.
2.     We asked, finally, what the “goal” is in unearthing and explaining our modern Will to Truth.
a.     Two central themes emerged: Foucault’s project could be seen as descriptive, but also (or either) as an act.  That is, he could be read as describing the rules and regulations of discourse, but also of trying to modify that discourse insofar as he describes it in his archaeological manner.